Εικόνες σελίδας
PDF
Ηλεκτρ. έκδοση
[graphic]

REMARKS ON THE PROGRESS OF CELESTIAL MECHANICS SINCE THE MIDDLE OF THE CENTURY.

PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS DELIVered before the AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY, DECEMBER 27, 1895.

BY DR. G. W. HILL.

THE application of mathematics to the solution of the problems presented by the motion of the heavenly bodies has had a larger degree of success than the same application in the case of the other departments of physics. This is probably due to two causes. The principal objects to be treated in the former case are visible every clear night, consequently the questions connected with them received earlier attention; while, in the latter case, the phenomena to be discussed must ofttimes be produced by artificial means in the laboratory; and the discovery of certain classes of them, as, for instance, the property of magnetism, may justly be attributed to accident. A second cause is undoubtedly to be found in the fact that the application of quantitative reasoning to what is usually denominated as physics generally leads to a more difficult department of mathematics than in the case of the motion of the heavenly bodies. In the latter we have but one independent variable, the time; while in the former generally several are present, which makes the difference of having to integrate ordinary differential equations or those which are partial. Thus it happens that, while the science of astro-mechanics is started by Newton, that of thermal conductivity receives its first treatment, at the hands of Fourier, more than a century later. In addition to these two causes, ever since the discovery of the telescope the application of optical means to the discovery of whatever might be found in the heavens has always had a fascination for mankind. And, as the ability to co-ordinate and correlate the facts observed much enhances the enjoyment of scientific occupation, it has resulted that many who began as observers ended as mathematical astronomers. Thus our science has had relatively a large number of cultivators.

A thoroughly satisfactory history of our subject is yet to be written. We have only either slight sketches of the whole, or elaborate treatments of special divisions of the science, and none of them coming down to recent times. Among the former may be mentioned Gautier's Essai historique sur le pro

blème des trois corps, which appeared in 1817. Also Laplace's historical chapters in the last volume of the Mécanique Céleste. Todhunter's History of the theories of attraction and the figure of the earth is an example of the latter class. Such books as Todhunter's—of which Delambre has given an earlier example in his Histoire de l'Astronomie-can hardly be regarded as history; they resemble rather extensive tables of contents of the literature examined, accompanied by short comments. However, in many cases, they are more useful to the student than formal histories would be, as, when judiciously compiled, they may, as epitomes in our libraries, take the place of a large mass of scientific literature. The History of Physical Astronomy, by Robert Grant, is a book that comes down to 1850, and professedly covers the whole of our subject. But only one third of this book is devoted to astro-mechanics, the rest dealing with what is really observational and descriptive astronomy. Moreover, the author indulges so much in diffusive veins of writing, that but a small fraction of the 200 pages is really given to purely historic statement. As far as the Lunar Theory is concerned, the third volume of M. Tisserand's Traité de Mécanique Céleste constitutes a fair history. But it must be borne in mind that the author's plan is to notice only the disquisitions having a first-class importance; hence his history is incomplete in this respect.

In America we are not well situated for investigations of this character, on account of the meagreness of our libraries. Of no inconsiderable number of memoirs and even books, having at least some importance in our subject, there exist no copies in the United States. Hence, should an American be inclined to undertake the task of writing the history of our subject, he must at least perform some of the work abroad.

In the present discourse it is proposed to touch very lightly the more important steps made since the middle of the century, the time at our disposal not admitting fuller treatment.

And first we will take up Delaunay's method, proposed for employment in the lunar theory, but quite readily extended to all classes of problems in dynamics. The first sketch of this method, given of course by the author himself, appeared in the Comptes Rendus of the Paris Academy of Sciences, in 1846. It professes to be merely an extract from a memoir offered for publication in the collections of the Academy, which must, however, have been afterwards withdrawn to make place for the two volumes of the Théorie du Mouvement de la Lune. When this extract is compared with the earlier chapters of the latter work, it is perceived that Delaunay has, to some extent, modified and improved his method in the interim between 1846 and 1860. In this long period nothing appeared from the author on this subject. He must have been profoundly engaged in

applying his method to the motion of the moon. Tisserand's exposition of this method is somewhat more brief than the author's own. But when the necessary modifications are introduced into Delaunay's procedures, to make them applicable to the more general case of the motion of a system of bodies, the establishment of the formulas can be rendered still more brief.

There is one point in reference to Delaunay's method which, as far as I am aware, has escaped notice. This method consists in a series of operations or transformations, in each of which the position of the moon in space is defined by six variables, the number three being doubled in order that the velocities, as well as the co-ordinates, may be expressed without differentials. The aim of the transformations is to make one half of these, which Poincaré has called the linear variables, continually approach constancy, while the other half, named the angular variables, continually approach a linear function of the time. But at any stage of the process the position of the moon, as well as its velocity, is definitely fixed by the six variables produced by the last transformation, provided that the proper degree of variability is attributed to them, just as, before any transformation was made, the six elements of elliptic motion, usually denominated osculating, defined them; the point of difference to be noticed being that the more the transformations are multiplied, the more complex becomes the character of the expression of the former quantities in terms of the latter. But, however great may be the number of transformations, the series evolved have always one consistent trait, viz., that the angular variables are involved in them only through cosines or sines of linear functions of these variables, the linear functions being formed with integral coefficients. Now, as in all this work we are obliged to employ infinite series, the question of their convergence is an extremely important one. The inquiry in this respect may be divided into two parts, mainly independent of each other. These are, convergence as respects the angular variables, and convergence as respects the linear variables. The first part is much the more simple. Regarding each of the coefficients of the series we employ as a whole, that is, representing it by a definite integral, it is quite easily perceived that the said series are both legitimate and convergent when, giving the angular variables the utmost range of values, still no two of the bodies can occupy the same point of space. In the contrary case the series are evidently divergent. This condition affords certain limiting conditions for the values of the linear variables. Could we trace these limiting conditions through all the transformations, and obtain by comparison the formulas to which these tend when the number of transformations is made infinite, we should be in possession of the conditions of stability of motion of the system of bodies. The second

part of the inquiry relates to the expression of the mentioned coefficients by infinite series proceeding according to powers and products of certain parameters which are functions of the linear variables. It is well known that, in the case of elliptic elements, Laplace and Cauchy almost simultaneously showed that the series are convergent when the eccentricity does not exceed a fraction which is about two-thirds. The determination of the conditions of convergence, after certain transformations have been made in the signification of the elements, is undoubtedly a more complex problem; nevertheless, it seems to be within the competency of analysis as it exists at present. The discovery of the criterion for the convergence of series proceeding according to powers and products of parameters is due to Cauchy, and is a most remarkable contribution to the science of mathematics. Supposing that the parameters begin from zero values, this criterion amounts to saying that the moment the function, which the series is to represent, ceases to be holomorphic, or becomes infinite, that moment the series ceases to be convergent. Consequently, if a space, having as many dimensions as there are parameters in the case, be conceived, and a surface be constructed in it formed by the consensus of all the points where the considered function ceases to be holomorphic, then, provided the values of the parameters define a point within this surface, that is, on the same side where lies the origin, the series will be convergent. Generally this surface will be closed, and, within it, the function will not take infinity as its value.

Without any mathematical reasoning the propriety of the principle just enunciated may be perceived. Since it is possible for the series in powers and products to give only one value for the function, the moment the latter may have any one of several values, the series fails to give them all; and, as there is no reason why any particular value should be selected, the conclusion must be that it does not represent any of them. Also, it is easy to see that, when the function takes infinity as its value, the series fails to represent it.

In applying this principle to the series involved in the treatment of the problem of many bodies by Delaunay's method, it appears, at first sight, as if we must have some finite representation of the coefficients in question in order to discover the particular points at which they cease to be holomorphic, such, for instance, as is given by an algebraic or transcendental equation. But this is not imperative, as it is often possible to make this discovery from certain recognized properties of the function considered, without being in possession of its form explicitly or implicitly. It appears probable that, in the class of cases considered, the mentioned coefficients can be represented by multiple definite integrals, all taken between the limits 0

« ΠροηγούμενηΣυνέχεια »