Εικόνες σελίδας
PDF
Ηλεκτρ. έκδοση

is expounded, and its analogue in space suggested. A tangent is defined as the limiting case of a secant, and an asymptote as a tangent at infinity. Desargues shows that the lines which join four points in a plane determine three pairs of lines in involution on any transversal, and from any conic through the four points another pair of lines can be obtained which are in involution with any two of the former. He proves that the points of intersection of the diagonals and the two pairs of opposite sides of any quadrilateral inscribed in a conic are a conjugate triad with respect to the conic, and when one of the three points is at infinity its polar is a diameter; but he fails to explain the case in which the quadrilateral is a parallelogram, although he had formed the conception of a straight line which was wholly at infinity. The book, therefore, may be fairly said to contain the fundamental theorems on involution, homology, poles and polars, and perspective.

The influence exerted by the lectures of Desargues on Descartes, Pascal, and the French geometricians of the seventeenth century was considerable; but the subject of projective geometry soon fell into oblivion, chiefly because the analytical geometry of Descartes was so much more powerful as a method of proof or discovery.

The researches of Kepler and Desargues will serve to remind us that as the geometry of the Greeks was not capable of much further extension, mathematicians were now beginning to seek for new methods of investigation, and were extending the conceptions of geometry. The invention of analytical geometry and of the infinitesimal calculus temporarily diverted attention from pure geometry, but at the beginning of the last century there was a revival of interest in it, and since then it has been a favourite subject of study with many mathematicians.

Mathematical knowledge at the close of the renaissance.

Thus by the beginning of the seventeenth century we may say that the fundamental principles of arithmetic, algebra,

theory of equations, and trigonometry had been laid down, and the outlines of the subjects as we know them had been traced. It must be, however, remembered that there were no good elementary text-books on these subjects; and a knowledge of them was therefore confined to those who could extract it from the ponderous treatises in which it lay buried. Though much of the modern algebraical and trigonometrical notation had been introduced, it was not familiar to mathematicians, nor was it even universally accepted; and it was not until the end of the seventeenth century that the language of these subjects was definitely fixed. Considering the absence of good text-books, I am inclined rather to admire the rapidity with which it came into universal use, than to cavil at the hesitation to trust to it alone which many writers showed.

If we turn to applied mathematics, we find, on the other hand, that the science of statics had made but little advance in the eighteen centuries that had elapsed since the time of Archimedes, while the foundations of dynamics were laid by Galileo only at the close of the sixteenth century. In fact, as we shall see later, it was not until the time of Newton that the science of mechanics was placed on a satisfactory basis. The fundamental conceptions of mechanics are difficult, but the ignorance of the principles of the subject shown by the mathematicians of this time is greater than would have been anticipated from their knowledge of pure mathematics.

With this exception, we may say that the principles of analytical geometry and of the infinitesimal calculus were needed before there was likely to be much further progress. The former was employed by Descartes in 1637, the latter was invented by Newton some thirty or forty years later, and their introduction may be taken as marking the commencement of the period of modern mathematics.

THIRD PERIOD.

Modern Mathematics.

The history of modern mathematics begins with the invention of analytical geometry and the infinitesimal calculus. The mathematics is far more complex than that produced in either of the preceding periods; but, during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, it may be generally described as characterized by the development of analysis, and its application to the phenomena of nature.

I continue the chronological arrangement of the subject. Chapter XV contains the history of the forty years from 1635 to 1675, and an account of the mathematical discoveries of Descartes, Cavalieri, Pascal, Wallis, Fermat, and Huygens. Chapter XVI is given up to a discussion of Newton's researches. Chapter XVII contains an account of the works of Leibnitz and his followers during the first half of the eighteenth century (including D'Alembert), and of the contemporary English school to the death of Maclaurin. The works of Euler, Lagrange, Laplace, and their contemporaries form the subject-matter of chapter XVIII.

Lastly, in chapter XIX I have added some notes on a few of the mathematicians of recent times; but I exclude all detailed reference to living writers, and partly because of this, partly for other reasons there given, the account of contemporary mathematics does not profess to cover the subject.

« ΠροηγούμενηΣυνέχεια »